The Price is Always Right

Last night I dreamt that I lived in a world parallel to ours, in Old Cork City in the Stated Unions of Columbia. The Columbians are an affluent and enlightened lot, but they suffer from a very peculiar madness: they consider Newton’s laws of motion and gravity to be ethically unjust and refuse to abide by them. It is clear to every Columbian that light objects soar while heavy objects must crash to the ground. Yes, scientists at Old Cork College have repeatedly shown that feathers and a bowling ball fall at the same speed in the absence of air resistance, but Columbians figure that gravity works differently in a perfect academic setting than it does in real life.

feathers bowling.gif
Source: Gizmodo

Since it is unfair for heavy things to fly while lighter objects are earthbound, heavier than air flight is banned in the SUC. Airlines are allowed to increase the weight of their zeppelins by no more than 5% from year to year, an arbitrary number arrived at after consultation with astrologers.

There are physicists in the Stated Unions, and their journals are full of lift equations and orbit calculations. Columbians have learned to ignore their physicist’s incessant calls for airplane and rocketry development, and their admonitions that starvation will not help man to soar. It’s quite obvious that a physicist’s job is to argue over string theory and quantum interpretations, flight is a simple, common sense issue, one that the public can handle quite well without the aid of experts. A few Columbians each year diet to near starvation and then jump off cliffs hoping to fly, but their numbers are small enough not to put any politician’s career in jeopardy.

In 1903, two Columbian bicycle repairmen named Orville and Wilbur Rong built an illegal airplane in secret. From a field outside the town of Puppy Eagle the brothers soared into the cold December air. For three seconds the only sound heard was the whine of the propeller and the rush of wind on the wings. Then, the sound of gunfire filled the air as state police promptly shot the Rong Flyer from the sky. The gathered public erupted in applause at the resolute reaction of law enforcement.

In my dream, I wondered at my countrymen’s reluctance to acquiesce to the simple laws of nature. Perhaps people rebel against the idea of a system beyond any person’s design, one that doesn’t follow any person’s wishes but imposes its implacable rules on all men. Perhaps the Columbians just need more time to come to grips with Newton’s formulas. After all, they were only published as late as 1687, barely three centuries prior.


In 1695, eight years after Newton’s Principia, English philosopher John Locke published a very short essay called Venditio, concerning pricing and the ethics thereof. Wasting no time, Locke kicks off by explaining the Law of One Price in an open market (emphasis mine):

Upon demand what is the measure that ought to regulate the price for which anyone sells so as to keep it within the bounds of equity and justice, I suppose it in short to be this: the market price at the place where he sells. Whosoever keeps to that in whatever he sells I think is free from cheat, extortion and oppression, or any guilt in whatever he sells, supposing no fallacy in his wares.

To explain this a little: A man will not sell the same wheat this year under 10 Shillings per bushel which the last year he sold for 5S. This is no extortion by the above said rule, because it is this year the market price, and if he should sell under that rate he would not do a beneficial thing to the consumers, because others then would buy up his corn at this low rate and sell it again to others at the market rate, and so they make profit off his weakness and share a part of his money. […]

But if it be said ’tis unlawful to sell the same corn for 10S this week which I sold the last year for week for 5s because it is worth no more now than it was then, having no new qualities put into it to make it better, I answer it is worth no more, ’tis true, in its natural value, because it will not feed more men nor better feed them than it did last year, but yet it is worth more in its political or marchand value, as I may so call it which lies in the proportion of the quantity of wheat to the proportion of money in that place and the need of one and the other.

Locke understood that when you come to a city with many buyers and sellers, and they all sell and buy wheat from each other at 10S, the only price you can sell (or buy) wheat at is 10S. Moved by some intuition of fairness you may want to sell it at last year’s price of 5S, but you can’t. Whoever buys it for 5S will immediately resell it for 10S to those who will actually consume it, you have simply given your profit away to an unproductive third party. You may want to sell your wheat for 20S because you’re greedy, but you can’t. No one will buy for 20S what they can get next door for 10S.

A single market will have the same price across it for a single good or service. What defines a single market is a group of buyers and sellers that are easily replaced by one another. That’s why the price of wheat in a shop down the street matters: the buyer can easily go there and get that price. That also why last year’s, or even yesterday’s, price in the same shop doesn’t matter: neither the buyer nor the seller can travel to yesterday and buy yesterday’s tomatoes at yesterday’s price. The price of tomatoes on Mars is more relevant to the tomato market in London than the price of tomatoes a week before; Mars is at least in principle available to trade tomatoes with.

Farming on Mars: NASA Ponders Food Supply for 2030s Mission
Credit: Pat Rawlings / NASA

Like Newton’s first law, which states that an object will not change its motion unless acted upon by a force, the Law of One Price is counterintuitive for the first 10 minutes of pondering it. At that point, it becomes so deeply obvious that one is shocked at how humans have lived for millennia without grasping it. Unfortunately, 10 minutes of thought are beyond the abilities of journalists and politicians to this very day.

The Guardian:

Burning Man tickets will be even more expensive this year thanks to a new Nevada entertainment tax that the state is requiring the festival to impose.

The price for the majority of tickets to the massive summer event in the Black Rock Desert, three hours north of Reno, has climbed from $390 to $424 for an individual ticket due to a 9% state tax that organizers have unsuccessfully tried to fight over the past month.

Quick, children, what’s the real price for Burning Man 2016 tickets, $390 or $424? The answer, of course, is that the only price of Burning Man tickets is exactly $840, that’s the price at which they are resold to the actual festival attendees. Burning Man organizers can keep a larger or smaller chunk of the $840 to themselves by raising or lowering the price, the state of Nevada can keep more or less of the $840 by changing the tax, but neither of them sets the price of $840.

Without nitpicking, let’s say that there are 70,000 tradable tickets available for Burning Man. The price of $840 is the only one at which exactly 70,000 people want to buy a ticket. Without changing the capacity or desirability of the festival, the only thing Burning Man organizers do by moving the price is deciding how much money to donate to Stub Hub and the resellers. They could have donated that money to poor attendees by giving some of them non-transferrable free admission (they do a little of it). They could have donated that money to charity. Instead, they simply donate 70,000 * $400 = $28,000,000 to ticket resellers for no good reason whatsoever. Hamilton on Broadway is donating $12,500,000 a year.

Jumping off a cliff and hoping to fly.


Of course, you may say, there are free markets and then there are hurricanes. When hurricane Sandy hit the tri-state area in 2012, many gas stations lost power and people at first were willing to pay $20 for a gallon of gas that cost $4 the week prior. This is such a novel and unusual situation… that John Locke described it with perfect precision 317 years prior:

To have a fuller view of this matter, let us suppose a merchant of Danzig sends two ships laden with corn, whereof the one puts into Dunkirk, where there is almost a famine for want of corn, and there he sells his wheat for 20S a bushel, whilst the other ship sells his at Ostend just by for 5s. Here it will be demanded whether it be not oppression and injustice to make such an advantage of their necessity at Dunkirk as to sell to them the same commodity at 20s per bushel which he sells for a quarter the price but twenty miles off? I answer no, because he sells at the market rate at the place where he is, but sells there no dearer to Thomas than he would to Richard. And if there he should sell for less than his corn would yield, he would only throw his profit into other men’s hands, who buying of him under the market rate would sell it again to others at the full rate it would yield. […]

Dunkirk is the market which the English merchant has carried his corn, and by reason of their necessity it proves a good one, and there he may sell his corn as it will yield at the market rate, for 20s per bushel.

Locke is correct that on a first order analysis, selling the corn (grain) at 5S in Ostend or 20S in Dunkirk are morally equivalent. If we also consider the effects of supply and demand, we can see that the ethical obligation is for the merchant to take his grain to Dunkirk, as his arrival there will help the neediest and immediately reduce wheat prices. The price of 20S is driven by the tiny supply of wheat available, even a single ship will increase that amount enough for the price to drop.

If New Jersey gas stations were allowed to sell gas at $20, the price would have stayed at that level for at most 3 or 4 hours. That’s how long it takes to fill up a tanker in Pennsylvania or Maryland and drive to Jersey. Who would be the suckers buying at $20 in the first few hours? Perhaps a doctor who must commute to a hospital where a single hour of her work is worth hundreds of dollars and the lives of patients.

New Jersey law prohibits “unreasonably excessive” raising of prices. In a state where fashion boutiques change the prices of jackets by 80% day to day on a whim, “unreasonably excessive” increases in the price of gas in a once-a-decade storm turned out to be 5%-10%. That number was arrived by lawyers setting precedents in courts, no one bothered to consult economists. Everyone knows that the job economists is to debate the impact of monetary policy on labor productivity in obscure journals. Prices are obviously a common sense issue that the public can handle quite well without the aid of experts.

Professor Locke, can you predict what happens when price “gouging” is capped at 5 or 10 percent:

Besides, as there can be no other measure set to a merchant’s gain but the market price where he comes, so if there were any other measure, as 5 or 10 per cent as the utmost justifiable profit, there would be no commerce in the world, and mankind would be deprived of the supply of foreign mutual conveniences of life. For the buyer, not knowing what the commodity cost the merchant to purchase and bring thither, could be under no tie of giving him the profit of 5 or 10 per cent, and so can have no other rule but of buying as cheap as he can, which turning often to the merchant’s downright loss when he comes to a bad market, if he has not the liberty on his side to sell as dear as he can when he comes to a good market. This obligation to certain loss often, without any certainty of reparation, will quickly put an end to merchandising.

What does it look it like when the “obligation to certain loss puts an end to merchandising”? It looks like a state where gas stations have gas in the ground, but no power in the grid to run the pumps. Many gas stations had generators that would power the pumps, but running the generators costs more than electricity from the grid does, and without raising prices by more than 10% that gas stations couldn’t break even while running generators. In case this isn’t clear: there is gas in the ground, there are pumps to pump the gas, there are generators to power the pumps, there are people desperate to buy the gas, there is a law that prevents them from doing so, there is someone dying in a hospital because their doctor can’t get there to help them.

Credit: Lucas Jackson / Reuters

But, it turns out that there weren’t enough people dying in hospitals to put governor Christie’s career in jeopardy.


A lot of people when they read The Rationality Sequences are rankled by Eliezer’s insistence that irrationality isn’t an inconsequential issue, but that almost everybody in the world is insane almost all of the time. A counterargument to Eliezer is that people have crazy beliefs when they don’t actually pay for having them. A person who disbelieves the multiple world interpretation of quantum mechanics suffers no worse harm than Eliezer’s stern disapproval. Holding crazy political views doesn’t cost a single person on the margin, since one person’s vote never counts.

The counterexample to that argument is this: they clapped.

Hurricane Fran hit North Carolina in September 1996, leaving part of the state without power in 92 degree heat. Food, baby formula and insulin were spoiling in idle refrigerators, and there was no ice to be found within 30 miles of Raleigh, NC. Fortunately, there was ice to be found 50 miles away from Raleigh in the city of Goldsboro, where four young entrepreneurs loaded two trucks with $1.75 bags of ice and drove to Raleigh. On the way, they used chainsaws to clear the road of fallen trees for themselves and for other grateful drivers.

The trucks parked in downtown Raleigh and began selling the bags of ice at $8 a pop, which almost no one refused to pay. As the line of Raleighites yearning for ice lengthened, the local police arrived at the scene to arrest the ice sellers and take the ice away, at gunpoint, from the people who desperately needed it, who had food and baby formula and insulin spoiling in the fridge. And many of these same people erupted in applause at the resolute reaction of law enforcement.


fantasy_zeppelin_photomanipulation_by_xt_hisashi-d5rk4bc
Credit: XT_Hisashi

This morning, I woke up from my dream, and for the few seconds before I remembered I lived in New York and not Old Cork, I was smiling. Zeppelins aren’t so bad: the drinks on board are better and there’s more legroom. But when people fight the law of prices, there are no winners, only losers.

18 thoughts on “The Price is Always Right

    1. That’s why it almost cracked the top 400 coolest things about Iceland. It was just edged out by AirBnBs without hot tubs (what’s the point?) and the passport control line at Keflavik (there are 8 lines, but they all direct people to a single old lady checking boarding passes and creating a monstrous bottleneck).

      Like

  1. I always liked the old Soviet joke:

    Angry commissar: “Why are you overcharging for this! The price is half as high across the street!”
    Shopkeeper: “So why don’t you buy from across the street?”
    Commissar: “They’re out of stock!”
    Shopkeeper: “Well, then when I run out of stock I promise to make *my* prices a *third* as high!”

    Liked by 2 people

  2. Wow, I didn’t know there were actual laws against price-gouging.

    Seen on Quora:

    Why isn’t there a price gouging law in India, to prevent shameless price escalation during emergencies?

    No answers.
    Makes me feel a little better about our parliament’s notorious time-wasting. Worse things they could be doing.
    An nice article in Forbes about floods closing Chennai airport in December last year
    http://www.forbes.com/sites/timworstall/2015/12/05/price-gouging-or-just-surge-pricing-in-india-with-chennai-airport-closed/#181fb5a4257c
    Concludes:

    You can call it surge pricing if you like but I’m perfectly happy with calling i[t] price gouging. It’s a good thing, it’s how scarce resources should be allocated. And thus we must rescind the laws against it, where they exist.

    PS: Typo in the subtitle- So why do we keep raging against in the 21st century? ….is missing an ‘it’

    Like

  3. Of course if this post is true you would have been able to find a Icelandic National Team football jersey to buy if you had been willing to pay someone enough for it. The situation regarding the jersey is illustrative of a way in which the price is not always right: coordination problems. The primary market may not have the correct price but this post posits that if it doesn’t, there would be a secondary market (legal or illegal, hard or easy to find, etc.) for football jersey’s. If this post is correct, you would be able to find someone who owns a jersey who is willing to give up the jersey for enough money. If you weren’t willing to pay that much then either the right price was too high for you or coordination problems were preventing you from accessing a willing seller at the right price.

    I don’t know if I explained my point well but neo-classical economics is posited on markets being completely efficient. This may provide a good tool to find a first order price but it is laughable if people think such things actually exist in reality. There apparently was not a completely efficient mechanism for finding a market equilibrium between people who have football jerseys and people who want football jerseys. E-Bay may help but of there are people in either group that don’t have access to E-Bay for whatever reason, this mechanism is still not completely efficient. If you took one path to finding someone willing to sell their jersey then you might have to pay a different price then you would if you took a different path. Both cannot be the right price.

    There are other reasons why a price might not be the “right” one. Some of this may stem from disagreement over what the right price should be defined to be (in technical terms two such options are “the market equilibrium found in a completely efficient market” and the “social equilibrium found in a completely efficient market perfect knowledge of social effects.”) Positive or negative externalities to a thing’s production or consumption (for example, the experiments in nuclear fusion that I am conducting in my garage may effect the price my neighbors home sells for but this would not necessarily be reflected in the price I pay for my experiments) can change what the right price is by some definitions. Having correct and perfect knowledge about such externalities is also an impossible goal in reality.

    There are further complications when one considers monopolist, monsoponist, or ogilopolist markets in situations where an efficient auxiliary market does not (or can not) exist or even when it does. One could still say the right price is the price the monopoly is willing to sell at, but this doesn’t fit either of the proposed above definitions nor your example about Burning Man tickets (the primary market is monopolist but the secondary market isn’t. I never said a monopoly has to be smart.) Maybe different situations require different definitions but the situations aren’t simple and a devout neo-claisscal economist won’t give answers matching reality.

    There are clear examples where the price isn’t right such as from the result of the coordination problems when you were trying to get an Icelandic football jersey. There are also competing reasonable definitions of what the “right” price is. The definition that the right price is the price something sells for in the terminal (primary, secondary, or more distant) market doesn’t always yield one number because in reality there can be separate terminal markets for the thing that have different equilibrium pricing. I am not saying that “the price is always wrong,” or that price gauging laws are justified (I’m not stating a position on that here at this time), but I am saying that “the price is not always right” if only because there isn’t always one price for a thing.

    Like

    1. From what I understand, your examples mostly come down to “there isn’t always an efficient market”. That’s certainly true. My point is that if you do find yourself in an efficient market (Hamilton tickets), trying to fight the resulting market price is pointless. And if there’s an efficient market and you shut it down (ice in Raleigh), many people will suffer because these people came to create the market for a reason.

      Like

      1. I will agree to that if one finds oneself in an efficient market then the market price is readily available and it would be foolish to claim a different price ass the true market price (the pendant in me wants to quibble on this and the nervous nellie in me wants to stop talking with people on the internet and eat a pizza). I do think that externalizes can provide a reason to fight the market price of a thing. As a less facetious example I will talk about two products that result in the production of sulfur dioxide which is a pollutant that causes damage: electrical power production and gasoline production. Both of these products (electrical power and gasoline) involve the production of sulfur dioxide in their creation or use and, in the US, the cap on sulfur dioxide emissions allowed by power plants has changed the price paid for electricity from the market (it increased it) and justifiably so I would claim. The requirement that cars have catalytic converters (in an effort to reduce the sulfur dioxide gasoline production releases into the atmosphere) has raised the price of cars (and thus likely lowered the cost of gasoline) but the idea to tax gasoline sales for the purpose of accounting for the costs to others from the burning of gasoline through the release of pollutants like sulfur dioxide (currently the purpose of taxes on gasoline in the United States is almost all to pay for roadway construction and maintenance) would also change the price of gasoline from the market price. Even if one disagrees with the point, there exists a point in fighting the market price.

        Also the statement that a government (or something else) should never (attempt to) shut down an efficient market (which I believe your arguments imply) cannot be fully supported by examples in which doing so was a bad thing. Doing a google search for “human organ market” provided me in the first two searches differning opinions on whether or not efficient markets for kidneys (to say nothing of hearts) should be allowed to exist. For my part, the reluctance I have for using absolutes leads me to not support the statement that there is never a good enough reason to forbid an efficient market. I have not seen an argument here that convinces me that it is impossible for such a situation (an efficient market that should be shut down) to exist.

        Maybe I’m still missing the point of the post. It happens a lot for me. Perhaps that is something I should fix.

        Like

Leave a comment